Immigration, Majority Rights, and Welfare State Solidarity
Liav Orgad’s new book, The Cultural Defense of Nations, could hardly have appeared at a more opportune moment. It represents a systematic effort to grapple with the core issues of national identity so much on the agenda of both the classical and new lands of immigration. It seeks to do so within the framework of liberal political and social theory while turning our sympathies toward majority cultures facing the “threat” of lost identity and dominance, a loss being brought about by both immigration and the multiculturalist policies of the past generation.
As recently as two or three years ago, liberal and progressive scholars and politicians shunned certain words, words that seemed redolent of exclusionary and discriminatory practices that had fortunately been overcome and which seemed very out of sync with the world of globalization, transnationalism, and non-discrimination. The idea of a dominant, mainstream Leitkultur was written off as reactionary, and even classical Weberian notions like the politically-constructed “feeling of belonging together,” Zusammengehörigkeitsgefühl, were disdained. Also in bad odor was any consideration of Homogenität, E. W. Böckenförde’s notion of relative social homogeneity as a foundation for liberal debate and conflict in society. Closure and boundedness were not good things, albeit sometimes necessary, and global justice rather than national class conflict was the order of the day. (I have taken up these matters at length here and here.) Second- and third-generation Rawlsians critiqued the master’s shortcomings in this area while stretching his conception of domestic overlapping consensus. Ethical and historical communities of obligation were, in short, not something to be frozen in time or even especially valued.
As we all know, things have changed rather quickly and dramatically. Outside the “illiberal democrats“ of central and eastern Europe, political leaders and theorists wish to remain fundamentally liberal while taking on board critiques raised during the past tumultuous year and those offered by national communitarians like Orgad. Orgad certainly wants to be closer to Michael Walzer than to Viktor Orbán, but the slope is very slippery and the ice on which he skates rather thin. Here he endorses an approach that: “centers on normative principles, values, and institutions, instead of actual practices, folkways, lifestyles, and cultural mores … [W]ithin the normative realm, the focal point is the constitution, rather than sociological concepts … Put differently, it is the constitutional, rather than national or societal identity. Moreover, the focus is only on core constitutional principles, the basic structure, and, exclusively, on those principles that are essential for citizenship in a given state … [T]here is no plea for moral identification, only for legal acceptance …”
Orgad – and not only Orgad – is stuck here somewhere between a Habermasian Verfassungspatriotismus and an endorsement of Leitkultur. Walzer moved from the communitarianism of Spheres of Justice (1983) to a more multicultural position arguing that nation states may “reproduce men and women of a certain sort: Norwegian, French, Dutch, or whatever,” but on the condition that they allow “minorities an equal freedom to organize their members, express their cultural values, and reproduce their way of life.”[1] Orgad worries that under current conditions of global migration and resettlement, such a regime would force some “needy” majority cultures to give too much away. Whether more serious efforts at immigrant integration, such as are now mooted nearly everywhere, would be enough to prevent “harm to liberal-democratic principles and institutions” and these “needy” cultures is uncertain. Immigrants as citizens-in-the-making in the juridical and civic sense may not be enough for a stout “cultural defense” of the nations to which they have come.
Although I suspect he might reject the claim, it seems to me Orgad’s position does lead him to Böckenfördian conclusions. The liberality of the liberal state is, in other words, nourished by and dependent on a certain value consensus, generally left undiscussed. In order to be able to dispute and fight democratically and stably over a certain range of matters, there needs to be a background consensus on numerous other matters, a consensus that goes sometimes to pre-political cultural as well as political values and not just rules, to justice and not just fairness. That agreement, in turn, cannot be limited to procedures or legality but must implicate historically and locally-produced sets of values, visions of justice, and a core of ethics.
To the Habermasian response that the democratic constitution and rational-discursive way of life themselves engender legitimacy without metaphysics and while accommodating citizens with diverse beliefs, the Orgadian skeptic might respond concerned – “trust” and “toleration” may indeed be generated through democratic constitutionalism. But it is more problematic in the social arena where legality alone may not be sufficient to generate legitimacy. While the existence of a democratic constitutional state makes higher demands of citizens than the rule of law alone might do, a redistributive social state “demands a more costly commitment and motivation, and these cannot simply be imposed by law” but rather are embedded in a civil society that is nourished by springs that one may term pre-political. Legitimacy, in other words, cannot spring from legality alone but comes also from places like culture and ethics. Community precedes contract.
Orgad is not overtly so interested in the welfare state, but it is here, I think, that the challenge of cultural and social fissiparousness combines with global neoliberal economics to undermine social solidarity and social welfare and create a culture of resentment and anxiety among native, majority populations that takes the form of cultural self-defense – from the AfD and similar populist parties that have grown enormously in Europe to Donald Trump. David Miller wondered years ago if socialism had to be communitarian, and that may be the case for strong welfare states as well. Trust and the willingness to be taxed and share are fragile things. Heavy immigration and diversity may disincline people from contributing to either redistribution or public goods. Identification with the history of the nation creates a commonality and connectedness that facilitate the legal instruments of redistribution. The civic virtues of a society thus inevitably reflect majority particularism as well as universal and civic principles while recognition of otherness may impede mutuality and redistribution.
In view of the likely pool of present and future immigrants to Europe in particular, a more serious integration commitment is essential – especially if a solidarity-based, redistributive social welfare regime is to be maintained in an era of capitalist hegemony. Massive enclaves of unintegrated people who may become not just alienated and hostile but lethal cannot be a good thing, especially as we come to see that illiberal alternative utopias are available to people. E Pluribus Unum is not so simple: Reciprocal trust, willingness to share, and readiness to invest in the commonweal are less where public diversity is greater. What this calls for is a policy of fordern and fördern. Immigration thus risks undermining the welfare state, itself a condition for equality and a functioning democracy. To preserve the both, accelerating integration is called for.
America has it easier. The U.S. is more successful in incorporating immigrants because it is marked by lower levels of solidarity and a weak welfare state. Immigrants are on their own – along with everyone else. The playing field is level, but there are no ladders for anyone, so the feeling of belonging together is less important and the incentive to acquire skills and one’s own contacts greater. Weak labor market regulation, for example, allows immigrants easier entry into the world of work, but it does so in a way that undermines labor as an organized force, further segmenting the labor market. Public discussion of waiving the minimum wage for immigrants isn’t really necessary; it simply happens “of its own”.
Integrating immigrants into and for the sake of viable democratic welfare states requires both bonds and bridges. The rule of law, cultural standardization, and social mobility are important. Strong anti-discrimination policies, accelerated language instruction, job training programs, residential and school integration, the discouragement of enclaves (though not necessarily of beachheads), and liberal naturalization policies are all a start. Adults must be placed in the labor market, including as many women as possible. In an age of fewer unskilled jobs, this is not as easy as in the days of voracious mines and mills and encompassing trade unions. Children must be in full-day schools, as ethnically integrated as possible with instruction only in the national language; the US experience with Spanish bilingual education has not been impressive.
What general lesson might we take away from Orgad’s treatment of immigration and sometimes-imperiled majority cultures? Clearly, immigrants join a sailing ship, whose future course they will help determine. Immigrants thereby come to share a common national identity, to which they make distinctive contributions. That ship, it has to be remembered, is a historic and civic community, a “contingent historical formation [that] is also the history of particular people … with their contingent array of practices, affiliations, customs, values, ideals, and allegiances” shaping and enforcing social, political, and legal institutions and cultures.
It is, then, a particular state and not just a liberal state; it is a contingent community of memory and experience united also by shared attachment to a body of principles. It is already well under way and sails through rough waters bearing a fragile social cargo. Under these circumstances, the task of creating an open and more capacious “we” requires not the dilution of membership’s meaning but rather the very social equality whose foundations and mechanisms immigration itself challenges. At a time when that social equality is increasingly undermined by fiscal crises and aggressive neoliberal advances, the integration of immigrants into the evolving national community should be seen as a key defense, a critical element in the construction of social solidarity and the ability to fight back.
[1] Michael Walzer, “Comment,” in Amy Gutman, ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton, 1994), p. 100. That Orgad is a liberal Israeli and Walzer is strongly identified with Israel is not irrelevant to the vexed question of vulnerable majorities and minority rights.
As a student for most of my adult life, and never having encountered any appreciation on the part of liberals for the cultural rights of majority cultures, the deep attachment Europeans may have for their cultural heritage, but always hearing about minority rights and our need to recognize the attachments non-European immigrants may have for their heritage, I would like to restate David Abraham’s opening observation about how novel Orgad’s argument is. At the same time, as I noted in my comment above to Orgad’s rejoinder, and in my comment to Dumbrava, Orgad’s thesis is framed “within the framework of liberal political and social theory,” as Abraham notes too. Orgad is an unusual liberal in being concerned about the threat that immigration and globalization pose to the majority cultures of Europe.
Yet, despite Abraham’s awareness about this neglect of majority right issues, both he and Orgad operate within a liberal framework that takes for granted the notion that majority cultural rights can only be affirmed within an established political and intellectual climate that supposes that European nations must be either open to diversity, or can only argue for majority in a liberal language that itself makes it very difficult, as pointed in the Dumbrava comment, to really defend the right of Europeans to preserve their ethnic identity and end mass immigration altogether. We are made to believe that majority cultures, national cultures, are “social constructs” rather than pre-modern communities with strong historical ancestries, strong kinship attachments, and ethnocentric tendencies, notwithstanding their current modern emphasis on individual rights.
Abraham’s objection to Orgad is simply that it is preferable to emphasize additional socialist spending as a way of integrating everyone within the nation’s multicultural setting, rather than endorsing constitutional approaches to majority problems, centred “on normative principles, values, and institutions”.
He thinks that a more open, broader, and tolerant sense of “we” can be nurtured more effectively through “social equality” measures. The best medicine, which would encourage the majority culture to feel at home in their increasingly diversifying nations, is to fight neoliberal economic policies, which also weaken immigrant integration.
For all his liberalism, he says that Orgad’s call for greater majority protections, is “very slippery” and can quickly create a climate in which the supposedly illiberal views of a Viktor Orbán may become acceptable. But what’s so unacceptable about Orbán, or the “AfD and similar populist parties that have grown enormously in Europe to Donald Trump”?
Again, Abraham is also operating within an unquestioned regime of cultural Marxist precepts which takes it for granted that any form of ethnic demands by Europeans, and calls for strict limitations on immigration, are inherently illiberal, however democratic these calls may be. Indeed, any perusal of the party platforms of “anti-immigrant” parties shows that they occupy the full political range in their socialistic, or libertarian, or ecologically oriented policies.
Instead, when facing terrorist acts by Muslims, epidemics of rapes in England, Sweden and now Germany, the answer of the “liberals” is to double down on their calls, as Abraham does, for more government spending on multicultural education and welfare spending, “anti-discrimination policies, accelerated language instruction, job training programs, residential and school integration, the discouragement of enclaves.”
But, speaking of socialistic, or social equality” measures, how is Sweden doing today in becoming the “humanitarian super power” of the world?
The stats speak for themselves:
*48 percent of immigrants of working age don’t work.
*Immigrants have not integrated; even after 15 years of residence 40 percent remain out of work.
*58 percent of welfare payments are allocated to immigrants.
*48 percent of children with low test scores are immigrants.
*Immigrants are not filling the skills-jobs economists claimed they would, which is why on average they earn 40 percent less than Swedes.
*Government spends about 4 billion a year settling new refugees.
*In 1990, Sweden had three “exclusion areas” (ghettoes inhabited primarily by non-Swedes); by 2004, it had 136, and 186 by 2006.
*The native Swedish population is being replaced; the immigrant population in Sweden has been increasing steadily from 14.5% in 2000, to 19.1% in 2010 to 21.5% in 2014.
*Swedes are now the minority in Malmö, the third largest city; and what is more is that the percentage of the foreign population in the younger age range, 0 to 44 years, has been steadily rising, from 47.0% in 2002 to 57.5% in 2013.
*Sweden, the most feminist country in the world, now has the second highest number of rapes in the world, after Lesotho in southern Africa, six times higher than the United States.
*In 2014, the cost of housing the 83.5% Swedish-born-immigrant population was around 4,44 billion kroners, while the foreign born population of 16.5% cost almost 8,88 billion kroners (not counting other expenses such as family allowances and old-age dependency support).
All these facts can be substantiated through proper Google searches, and some of them come from the Kurdish-Swedish eocnomist Tino Sanandaji.
I forwarded this reply to Abraham, and here is his answer, which I told him I would post here and he did not object:
==
Dear Frans,
There is no question that nations develop historically, and that that history is ethnic, linguistic, religious, and numerous other things. But those national identities are not static, and the integration of newcomers will change both the existing culture and the immigrants. Identities were not frozen in 1848, 1870 or 1914 or 1990. It is a dynamic process. Overlaying that historical process are political processes that help steer the formation of ethnic identities. I think Weber had that right. I dislike multiculturalism intensely and do not support group minority rights. I am an integrationist who supports the welfare state, both as a redistributional matter and as a mechanism for creating social solidarities. Some groups are definitely more difficult to integrate than others, and Muslims may be the toughest of all. While Koreans seem to need only one generation to master the elite universities and philharmonic orchestras of North America, Mexican peasants have it harder and Arab peasants harder still. The integration mechanism requires,a s Merkel put it in happier days, fordern and fördern.
Best,
David
=======
My reply: The claim that nations develop historically, that identities are not fixed, is a common one among liberal promoters of mass immigration, but it is a very misleading claim. Just because nations develop historically, it does not follow that they have always developed by way of mass migration movements. First, this claim can be easily refuted by showing that, to this day, non-European nations are developing historically without immigration. In fact, immobility is typical for the vast majority of the world’s population to this day: Over 98 percent of the people in less developed countries in 2005 were born in the country where they reside. Immigrants have accounted for a mere 1.4-1.6% of Asia’s population over the past twenty years.
Moreover, even for the West, cultural and ethnic identities have changed over time, but never through a program of mass immigration imposed by the governing elites. To take England as an example: One cannot compare the episodic migrations of genetically related people into England over many centuries with the current program of mass immigration from all over the world in the last few decades. What is transpiring in England today started in 1948 when the British Nationality Act affirmed the right of Commonwealth citizens (including those of newly independent Commonwealth countries like India) to settle in the United Kingdom. It was from this point on that non-white colonization started to increase steadily, so that by 2012 the proportion of white British had dropped from 87.5% of the population in 2001 to 80.5%. This has come with the forced implementation of diversity and the marginalization of English culture across all schools.
The same, fundamentally, holds true even for settler nations such as Canada. A few facts will suffice to refute Abraham and Kymlicka: as of 1971, Canada was 96% ethnically European, or White. It was only after the institutionalization of official multiculturalism in 1971 that immigrants from Africa, the Caribbean, Latin America, the Middle East and Asia at large started to arrive in large numbers. Of the 1.5 million who came between 1971 and 1981, 33 percent came from Asia, 16 percent from the Caribbean and South America and 5.5 percent from Africa. In the period 1991-2001, immigrants of European origin fell below 20 percent at the same time that Asian immigration soared to nearly 60 percent. Canada’s visible minority population has been growing much faster than its total population: 22 percent growth from 1996 to 2001 versus 4 percent growth in the general population. Today, roughly one out of every four people in Canada is a member of a visible minority.
This reality about Canada had no precedent in its history, and the notion that Canada was developing historically to become what it has become is simply false and intended to mislead students.